
So Much for Conservative Judicial Restraint
Making sense of a Supreme Court role reversal on the issue of standing.
WHAT DOES THE SUPREME COURT DO? There are two main schools of thought. One view has it that the Court settles concrete disputes between adverse parties. Although the Court interprets the law, it does so only as a means of resolving the controversy at hand. Under the other view, the Court still hears casesāit doesnāt pronounce on hypothetical questionsābut its true function is to uphold the rule of law in a broader sense. The Court defends, guides, and extends the nationās norms and values, and it holds the other branches of government to account.
Letās follow Hart and Wechslerās The Federal Courts and the Federal System, the leading textbook in this area, in calling these the ādispute resolutionā model and the ālaw declarationā model. If youād studied that treatise recently, you couldāve convinced yourself that thereās a clear political divide over these models. The Warren Court opened the courthouse doors to more litigants. The Rehnquist Court shut them again. Justice William O. Douglas (the outspoken progressive known as āWild Billā) argued that the trees have standing to sue. Justice Antonin Scalia (who needs no introduction) railed against letting citizens sue simply for suffering āmental displeasureā at the misuse of their tax dollars. The law declaration model is āliberal,ā you mightāve assumed, the dispute resolution model āconservative.ā
Not anymore.
Last month, the Supreme Court invalidated the Biden administrationās student loan forgiveness plan. A statute empowers the secretary of education to āwaive or modifyā provisions of the federal student loan program during a national emergency. Late last year, Secretary Miguel Cardona invoked the COVID-19 pandemic as grounds to cancel around $430 billion in federal student loans. In Biden v. Nebraska, the Courtās six-justice conservative majority held, in an opinion by Chief Justice Roberts, that the secretary had effectively tried not to āwaive or modifyā some loan requirements, but to āexhaustive[ly] rewrit[e]ā the Education Act.
That may well be correct. But whom did the scheme injure? As the majority acknowledged, a plaintiff needs standing to sue; it needs āa āpersonal stakeā in the case.ā It must point to a āconcrete and imminent harm,ā particular to itself, involving āa legally protected interest, like property or money.ā Who could meet these criteria in a suit over the Biden administrationās loan writeoff?
According to the majority, the state of Missouri could. Well, not exactly. But Missouri could enlist the Missouri Higher Education Loan Authority (MOHELA) as its proxy. MOHELA services federal student loans. It loses revenue if loans are canceled. And some of MOHELAās revenue is used to fund education initiatives and scholarship programs that benefit Missouriās students. Because MOHELA serves this āpublic function,ā the majority ruled, an injury to it counts as an injury to Missouri.
The problem with this reasoning is that MOHELA is a distinct legal entity. As a public corporation, it could have filed a lawsuit for itself. It didnāt. As a public corporation, its assets and debts are its own. A loss of revenue on its part does not pass through to Missouri. Not surprisingly, Missouri had never before tried to sue on MOHELAās behalf.
āUnder our usual standing rules,ā Justice Kagan objected, in a seething dissent for the Courtās three liberals, this āseparation would matter.ā She chastised the majority for downplaying the fact that MOHELAās āeconomic losses (1) are not passed on to the State and (2) can be rectified (if there is legal wrong) without the Stateās help.ā Nor did it matter that some of MOHELAās revenue flows back to Missouri students. That, Kagan explained, is a harm not to Missouriās government, but to Missouriās citizens. A state government lacks standing to sue, as its citizensā guardianāas āparens patriaeāāa federal government equally charged with protecting those citizensā rights.
But what really galled Kagan was how the majority, in deciding to hear the case, had āexceed[ed] the permissible boundaries of the judicial role.ā The rules of standing are supposed to ākeep courts acting like courts,ā she wrote. They are supposed to ensure that the justices āsend political issues to political institutionsāāthe executive and legislative branchesāand āretain only legal controversies, brought by plaintiffs who have suffered real legal injury.ā In Biden v. Nebraska, the Court failed to do this. The majority went on, in Kaganās view, to botch the case on the merits as well. āIn every respect,ā she concluded, āthe Court today exceeds its proper, limited role in our Nationās governance.ā
TWENTY YEARS AGO, the Environmental Protection Agency denied a petition urging it to set greenhouse-gas emission standards for new motor vehicles. The state of Massachusetts challenged the EPAās decision. The federal government argued that the state lacked standingāthat it could not point to a particularized injury caused by the EPA and redressable by a court order. The Supreme Court declared that a state government is āentitled to special solicitude in our standing analysis,ā and allowed the suit to proceed.
Dissenting in Massachusetts v. EPA (2007), Chief Justice Roberts opposed ārelaxingā the Courtās standing requirements simply ābecause asserted injuries are pressed by a State.ā Nothing about a stateās status as parens patriae, he insisted, ādilutes the bedrock requirement of showing injury, causation, and redressability.ā Whatās more, he continued, a state lacks āstanding to assert a quasi-sovereign interestāas opposed to a direct injuryāagainst the Federal Government.ā
āThe constitutional role of the courts,ā Roberts wrote, āis to decide concrete casesānot to serve as a convenient forum for policy debates.ā The āCourtās standing jurisprudence . . . recognizes that redress of [political] grievances . . . is the function of Congress and the Chief Executive.ā The principles of standing ensure āthat courts function as courts,ā and they must be ātaken seriously as a matter of judicial self-restraint.ā In Massachusetts v. EPA, Roberts complained, the Court failed to do this. It ātransgress[ed] the properāand properly limitedārole of the courts in a democratic society.ā
Obviously, the parallels between Robertsās past dissent and Kaganās present one are remarkable. The ethos of judicial restraint does not belong to one faction, one party, or one side. As Kagan observes, āJustices throughout history have raised the alarm when the Court has overreached.ā
Yet there is a lamentable pattern here. Generation after generation, justices express views about the ādispute resolutionā and ālaw declarationā models that seem to track their feelings about which cases they, personally, would prefer to hear. The rules of standing were formalized by Justice Louis Brandeis, a progressive who wanted to protect New Deal legislation from legal challenge. They were later disparaged by Justice Harry Blackmun, a progressive who wanted to allow the Sierra Club to litigate environmental issues. They were loosened when a liberal majority that included Kagan decided, over a dissent that included Roberts, to strike down the Defense of Marriage Act. They were loosened again when a conservative majority led by Roberts decided, over a dissent led by Kagan, to strike down the Biden administrationās student-loan forgiveness program.
In Massachusetts v. EPA, Roberts urged the Court not to make standing into a manipulable ālawyerās game.ā In Biden v. Nebraska, Kagan threw those words back at him. The real lawyerās game, it seems, is to wave the flag of judicial restraint only as convenience dictates. And thatās a discouraging thought.